It is in the same vain of following Greek popular opinion and opposing Plato’s political philosophy, that Aristotle defines the man of action, the politikos, as a phronimos, an understanding man, as opposed to the sophos, the wise man, whom Plato had wanted to rule the city1. The phronimos understands2 1140b9“3what is good for himself and what is good for men in general. ” In his definition already, Aristotle limited4 the competence of the phronimos in particular and of the political life in general. He5 wanted to show the limitations of action by limiting it to what is merely good for people. If we want to know, independent of philosophical interpretation and the philosophical separation of action from thought, the current Greek6 opinion of the human capacity of phronein, of understanding and this on its highest level, we may do well to remember the last lines with which Sophocles concludes7 the intensely political play of the Antigoné8, and which, curiously enough, contain some of the key words which later were to play such an important role in Aristotle’s political philosophy; such as10 eudaimonia, the awareness of having a good life, phronein, the understanding of it, and11 logoi,12 a way of life in general rather than the mere physical faculty of being able to talk, as logos also is meant14 in Aristotle’s definition of man as logon echôn, as being able to live in the manner of speech. Pollô to phronein eudaimonias/ prôton hyparchei; ... megaloi de logoi/ megalas plégas tôn hyperauchôn/ apoteisantes/ géra to phronein edidaxan. Understanding is by far the first thing15 inherent and necessary for a blessed life; ... and16 great words, if they responded to17 and paid back18 the great blows dealt by the divine19 powers, will have taught under- standing20 (insight) when we are old21.”22 Here, action and thought are almost one and the same, summed up as it were and bound together in the great words with which man meets his destiny and asserts24 himself in his essentially human condition. This he can do only if he lives together with others in the way of a polis, if he lives a political life in the original sense of the word; only thus can he be heard and make his words the permanent witness of otherwise changing circumstances and passing events. To find the right words, to be equal in greatness in words to the greatness of whatever may happen teaches insight and understanding; this insight is finally |9 eudaimonia, blessedness or happiness (or whatever other word we may try to translate the untranslatable), because it is the state in which the meaningfulness of the human condition as a whole is present and noticed by25 one particular human being. All this belonged for the Greeks to the life in the polis in general and expressed their particular political way26 of life. The reality of action and of thought were27 the words in which they uttered themselves and were heard by others. There was therefore no contradiction or opposition between the reality of action and the spirituality of thought, for both remained without reality as long as they remained without words. Not real and, by the28 same token, not political was only speechlessness-- mute violence29, mute suffering30, and the inarticulateness, not of passion, but of blind desire. Non-real was that what could not make itself permanently at home31 in the world of men32, in33 the polis which could not strike out with such force into34 the world35 of audible and visible appearance36 that it would be reasonably sure not to be forgotten. The same fundamental attitude to speech is expressed in a nonpoetical way in the words which the sophist Gorgias is supposed to have taught his followers37 and which Plato quotes as follows38: Gorgias,39 Pasa hé praxis kai hé kyrôsis dia logôn esti: all action and sovereignty exists through words. Only through words can human action acquire its dignity; or rather only in sofar action is not aneu logou, without word, has it meaning. And meaningfulness of the whole human condition in its entirety and in all its aspects is guaranteed beyond doubt wherever it speaks and is being heard by others. The sovereignty of men began where this possible meaningfulness of human life, which physei, by nature, belonged to the human condition, had found its corresponding body politic, which was the polis, because here speaking had become [metamark (text connection)]a daily way of life, (the politeuesthai and agoreuesthai, the politicizing and constant talking on the market place were indeed the concrete content of everyday life of a Greek citizen). (The apparent contradiction in Aristotle’s definition of man as a dzôon politikon and logon echôn, that it on one hand meant the distinction between Greeks and other nations, between free men40 and slaves, and therefore--like all political notions according to A.-- could not be physei, by nature, but nomô, by man-made institution, while, on the other he insists that man is by nature “political, is solved if we remember that the faculty of speech for A. was on one hand something belonging to the nature of man insofar as he iscf. distinguished from animal, and on the other, belonging to the Greeks in a polis insofar as only they have succeeded41 to eliminate brutishness altogether. Under no circumstances can this contradiction42 be solved by the current modern interpretation according to which men are by nature sociable and like to live together or have to, as other animals with herd instincts. One should not forget that the word “political” has only for us, but not43 to Greek ears, an altogether generalized meaning; To Aristotle, it was the adjective of the noun polis, a special form of government, or rather of living together, different, for instance, from kingship or |10 [metamark (text connection)]basileia, which was an earlier Greek way of living together, or from despotism, which was the form of government of Asian empires. To be a dzôon politikon meant to lead a truly human life in the polis, as the highest possible way of life, and to be a “political being” by nature meant to have the natural faculty of speech, which however led to true human sovereignty only in the polis.) | It is in the same vain of following Greek popular opinion and opposing Plato’s political philosophy, that Aristotle defines the man of action, the politikos, as a phronimos, an understanding man, as opposed to the sophos, the wise man. The phronimos is understand2 1140b9”3what is good for himself and what is good for men in general This definition is already typical of Aristotle’s philosophy who wanted to limit4 the competence of the phronimos in particular and of the political life in general. In other words, he5 wanted to show the limitations of action by limiting it to what is merely good for people. If we want to know, independent of philosophical interpretation and the philosophical separation of action from thought, the Greek current6 opinion of the human capacity of phronein, of understanding and this on its highest level, we may do well to remember the last lines with which Sophocles concluded7 the intensely political play of the Anitogoné8, and in9 which, curiously enough, contain some of the key words which later were to play such an important role in Aristotle’s political philosophy, especially10 eudaimonia, the awareness of having a good life, phronein, the understanding of it, logoi as12 a way of life in general rather than as13 the mere physical faculty of being able to talk, as it then occurs14 in Aristotle’s definition of man as logon echôn, as being able to live in the manner of speech. Pollô to phronein eudaimonias/ prôton hyparchei; ... megaloi de logoi/ megalas plégas tôn hyperauchôn/ apoteisantes/ géra to phronein edidaxan. Understanding is by far and above all15 inherent and necessary for a blessed life; ... but16 great words with which we pay back17 and respond to18 the great blows dealt by the higher19 powers teach when we are old understanding20 (insight). Here, action and thought are almost one and the same, summed up as it were and bound together in the great words with which man meets his destiny on earth23 and assert24 himself in his essentially human condition. This he can do only if he lives together with others in the way of a polis, if he lives a political life in the original sense of the word; only thus can he be heard and make his words the permanent witness of otherwise changing circumstances and passing events. To find the right words, to be equal in greatness in words to the greatness of whatever may happen teaches insight and understanding; this insight is finally |9 eudaimonia, blessedness or happiness (or whatever other word we may try to translate the untranslatable), because it is the state in which the meaningfulness of the human condition as a whole is revealed at every single moment to25 one particular human being. But if we prefer a non-poetical expression26 of the same fundamental Gorgias29, attitude30, we may simply go back to Plato who,31 in the Gorgias32, quotes33 the current opinion on34 the role35 of “words” as36 that what makes both, thought an action, meaningful37 and permanent38: Pasa hépraxis kai hé kyrôsis dia logôn esti: all action and sovereignty exists through words. Only through words can human action acquire its dignity; or rather only insofar action is not aneu logou, without word, has it meaning. And meaningfulness of the whole human condition in its entirety and in all its aspects is guaranteed beyond doubt wherever it speaks and is being heard by others. The sovereignty of men began where this possible meaningfulness of human life, which physei, by nature, belonged to the human condition, had found its corresponding body politic, which was the polis, because here speaking had become a daily way of life, (the politeuesthai and agoreuesthai, the politicizing and constant talking on the market place were indeed the concrete content of everyday life of a Greek citizen). (The apparent contradiction in Aristotle’s definition of man as a dzôon politikon and logon echôn, that it on one hand meant the distinction between Greeks and other nations, between free man40 and slaves, and therefore -- like all political notions according to A. -- could not be physei, by nature, but nomô, by man-made institution, while, on the other he insists that man is by nature “political, is solved if we remember that the faculty of speech for A. was on one hand something belonging to the nature of man insofar as he iscf. distinguished from animal, and on the other, belonging to the Greeks in a polis insofar as only they have succedeed41 to eliminate brutishness altogether. Under no circumstances can this conradiction42 be solved by the current modern interpretation according to which men are by nature sociable and like to live together or have to, as other animals with herd instincts. One should not forget that the word “political” has only for us, but to Greek ears, an altogether generalized meaning; To Aristotle, it was the adjective of the noun polis, a special form of government, or rather of living together, different, for instance, from kingship or |10 basileia, which was an earlier Greek way of living together, or from despotism, which was the form of government of Asian empires. To be a dzôon politikon meant to lead a truly human life in the polis, as the highest possible way of life, and to be a “political being” by nature meant to have the natural faculty of speech, which however led to true human sovereignty only in the polis.) |