For his own time and its immediate prospects, Montesquieu has the following1 to say: “The majority of the nations of Europe are still ruled by customs. But if |4 through a long misuse2 of power, if through some large conquest, despotism would3 establish itself at a given point, there would be neither customs nor climate which could4 resist; and in this beautiful part of the world, human nature5 would suffer, at least for a time, the insults which have been inflicted on it in the three others.” (Esprit des Lois, Book vii, ch. 8)6 | For his own time and its immediate prospects, Montesquieu had the following1 to say: “The majority of the nations of Europe are still ruled by customs. But if through a long misuse2 of power, if through some large conquest, despotism would3 establish itself at a given point, there would be neither customs nor climate which could4 resist; and in this beautiful part of the world, human natures5 would suffer, at least for a time, the insults which have been inflicted on it in the three others.” (ibidem, Book VII, ch. 8) In this passage, Montesquieu outlines the political dangers to a political body which is held together by customs and traditions only, that is by the mere binding force of morality. The dangers could appear from within, as misuse of power, or from without, as agression; the factor which eventually would bring the downfall of customs about in the beginning 19th century, he could not foresee; it came from that radical change of the modern world which we call the industrial revolution; this, certainly, is the greatest revolution in the shortest span of time mankind has ever witnessed; it changed in a few decades our whole globe more radically than the whole three thousand years of recorded history before it. Reconsidering Montesquieu fears which were voiced almost 100 years before this revolution had taken place in its whole magnitude, it is tempting, even though perhaps a bit idle, to reflect on the probable course of European civilization without the impact of this one, all-overriding factor. One conclusion seems inescapable: the great change took place within a political framework whose fundaments were no longer secure and overtook therefore a society which, although it was still able to understand and to judge, was no longer in a position to give account of its categories of understanding and standards of judgment if these should be challenged seriously. In other words, Montesquieu fears, |11 which sound so strange in the eighteenth and would sound so commonplace in the nineteenth century, may at least give us a hint for the explanation--not of totalitarianism or any other specific modern event but--of the disturbing fact that our great tradition has remained so peculiarly silent, so obviously wanting in productive replies, when challenged by the “moral” and political questions of our own time. The very sources from which such answers should have flown had dried up even before the debris of the caved in framework, within which understanding and judging could orient themselves, had buried them.6 | For his own time and its immediate prospects, Montesquieu had this1 to say: “The majority of the nations of Europe are still ruled by customs. But if through a long abuse2 of power, if through some large conquest, despotism should3 establish itself at a given point, there would be neither customs nor climate to4 resist; and in this beautiful part of the world, human nature5 would suffer, at least for a time, the insults which have been inflicted on it in the three others.” In this passage, Montesquieu outlines the political dangers to a political body which is held together only by customs and traditions, that is by the mere binding force of morality. The dangers could appear from within, as misuse of power, or from without, as aggression. The factor which would eventually bring about the downfall of customs in the early nineteenth century, he could not foresee. It came from that radical change in the world which we call the industrial revolution, certainly the greatest revolution in the shortest span of time mankind has ever witnessed; in a few decades it changed our whole globe more radically than all the three thousand years of recorded history before it. Reconsidering Montesquieu’s fears, which were voiced almost 100 years before this revolution developed its full force, it is tempting to reflect on the probable course of European civilization without the impact of this one, all-overriding factor. One conclusion seems inescapable: the great change took place within a political framework whose foundations were no longer secure and therefore overtook a society which, although it was still able to understand and to judge, could no longer give an account of its categories of understanding and standards of judgement when they were seriously challenged. In other words, Montesquieu’s fears which sound so strange in the eighteenth century and would have sounded so commonplace in the nineteenth, may at least give us a hint of the explanation, not of totalitarianism or any other specific modern event, but of the disturbing fact that our great tradition has remained so peculiarly silent, so obviously wanting in productive replies, when challenged by the “moral” and political questions of our own time. The very sources from which such answers should have sprung had dried up. The very framework within which understanding and judging could arise is gone.6 |