[metamark (text connection)]In striking opposition to the scarcity of sources in Hebrew and early Christian writings stands the overpowering influence of Plato’s myth of a Hereafter, with which he concludes so many of his political dialogues, on political thought of antiquity and later on Christian teaching. Between Plato and the secular victory of Christianity which brought with its the religious sanction of the doctrine of Hell (so that from then on this became so general a feature of the Christian world that political treatises did not need to mention it specifically), there is hardly an important discussion of political problems (with the great exception of Aristotle’s work, however) which did not conclude with an imitation of the Platonian myth. For it is Plato, and not the strictly Jewish-Christian religious sources, who is the most important forerunner of Dante’s elaborate descriptions; in him we find already the geographical separation of Hell, Purgatory and Paradise, and not merely the concept of final judgment about eternal life or eternal death and the hint at possible punishment after death.1 The purely political implications of Plato’s myth in the last book of the Republic, as well as the concluding parts of the2 Phaidon and the3 Gorgias, are indisputable. In the Republic, it4 corresponds to the story of the cave, which is the center of the whole work and which is not a myth but an allegory, destined5 for the few who are able,6 without hope7 or fear to perform8 the Platonic περιαγωγή9, the turning around from the shadowy life of seeming reality to the clear sky of ideas. Life with the11 ideas, while it clearly alienated them from12 the life of the polis, taught the few13 true standards of all life, including political affairs, in which, however, they were15 no longer to16 be interested for their own sake17. Only the fear of being ruled by the multitude could arouse the few to fulfill their political duties. These18 who could understand the story of the cave were not supposed to believe the concluding myth about final reward and punishment. Not only did those who had19 grasped the truth of the ideas as transcendent standards need no more20 tangible transcendence like an explicit21 life after death; it would not even have made22 much sense insofar as23 the story of the cave already describes life on earth as a kind of Underworld, and this |21 [metamark (text connection)]sense is reinforced by24 Plato’s use of the words eidôlon and25 skia which were the key words of Homer’s description of Hades in the Odyssey so that26 the whole story reads27 like an exact28 reply to Homer:30 not the soul is the shadow and not32 its life after death the purposeless insustantial motion33 in the Underworld34, but the bodily life of ordinary mortals who do not succed35 in turning away from the cave of earthly life; our life on earth is life in an Underworld36, our body is the shadow and our only reality is the soul. Since the truth of the ideas is self-revealing and therefore37 self-evident, the true standards for earthly life can never be satisfactorily argued out and demonstrated. The multitude which lacks the eye for the invisible measurement of all visible things, needs belief in a stark bodily transcendence in which it does not hold truth itself but only its “myth”. Whether or not Plato himself believed in the immortality of the soul, the myth of graduated bodily punishment after death (which since it is bodily even contradicts the theory that only the soul, not the body is immortal) is clearly the invention of a philosophy which deemed public affairs, the affairs in which all are equally involved, secondary and therefore subject to the rule of a truth which is accessible only to a few. The few cannot persuade the multitude of truth because truth cannot become the object of persuasion and persuasion is the only way to deal with the multitude (peithein τὰ πλήθη and rhetoric being the specifically political modes of speech while philosophizing, dialegein, is always carried through in the mode of autos autô, of one person talking to one other). But while the multitude cannot be instructed in the doctrine of truth, it can be persuaded to believe an opinion as though this opinion were the truth. The appropriate opinion which carries the truth of the few to the multitude is the belief in Hell; persuading the citizens of its existence will make them behave as though they knew the truth. In other words, the doctrine of Hell in Plato is clearly a political instrument invented for political purposes. This is equally obvious in the concluding myths of the Phaidon and the Gorgias, though we do not have there a corresponding allegory that tells |22 [metamark (text connection)]the philosophical truth like the cave story in the Republic. The Phaidon is not primarily the dialogue on the soul’s immortality, but “a revised Apology more persuasive than the speech (Socrates) made in (his) defence before the judges.” And in Gorgias, which in some ways is the first attempt to solve those problems of justice which later were the subject of the Republic, Socrates brings up his myth, still with great diffidence and clearly indicating that he does not take it too seriously, after he has failed to persuade the masters of rhetoric, i.e. of the argument proper for political affairs, and thus has found out that in this realm it cannot be “proved” that it is better to suffer wrong than do wrong. No doubt, speculations about life after death and descriptions of the Hereafter are as old as the conscious life of man on earth. Still, it may be true that we find in Plato for “the first time in the history of literature that any such legend (sc. of punishment and reward among the dead) has been definitely enlisted in the service of righteousness”, i.e. in the service of public, political life. This seems confirmed by the fact that the Platonic myth was so eagerly used by purely secular writers in antiquity, who as clearly as Plato indicated that they did not seriously believe in it, while, on the other hand, the the Christian creed shows no such doctrine of Hell as long as Christianity remained without secular interests and responsibilities. On the contrary, Christian writers during the first centuries almost unanimously believed in a mission of Christ to the Underworld whose main purpose had been to liquidate Hell, to defeat Satan and to liberate the souls of dead sinners, as he had liberated the souls of Christians, from death and punishment. It looks as though the origin of this doctrine was primarily political and that] and it continued to be used for political purposes; that it played no noticeable role in Christianity during the centuries of a purely religious development and received its religious sanction only in the early Middle Ages when political necessity confronted the Church, as it had ancient philosophy, with the old perplexity of enforcing absolute standards |23 [metamark (text connection)] on a realm of life whose very essence seems to be relativity, and this under the eternal human condition where the worst that man can do to man is to kill him, that is to bring about what one day is bound to happen to him anyhow. The “improvement” on this condition proposed in the doctrine of Hell is precisely that punishment can mean more than eternal death, namely eternal suffering in which the souls yearn for death. In Plato, it frankly substitutes insight into truth and thus gives human understanding a reliability which it could not possibly have otherwise; in Roman antiquity and in a considerably mellowed form, it is destined to enforce and encourage honorable behavior, until finally during the centuries of undisputed Christian authority in religious as well as secular matters, it was apparently taught on the assumption that the stings of conscience were not a too reliable punishment[metamark (text connection)] or, for that matter, guide of behavior. (The development in Christianity itself is clearly indicated in the fourth Lateran Council’s condemnation (in 1215) of the teaching that “hell is not a special place, but that the man who exists in a state of deadly sin finds hell in his own self” and the Church’s rejection of Origin’s opinion that “the fire of hell consisted as much in the stings of conscience as in material torment or the body.”)38 | In striking opposition to the scarcity of sources in Hebrew and early Christian writings stands the overpowering influence of Plato’s myth of a Hereafter, with which he concludes so many of his political dialogues, on political thought of antiquity and later on Christian teaching. Between Plato and the secular victory of Christianity which brought with it the religious sanction of the doctrine of Hell (so that from then on this became so general a feature of the Christian world that political treatises did not need to mention it specifically), there is hardly an important discussion of political problems (with the great exception of Aristotle’s work, however) which did not conclude with an imitation of the Platonian myth. For it is Plato, and not the strictly Jewish-Christian religious sources, who is the most important forerunner of Dante’s elaborate descriptions; in him we find already the geographical separation of Hell, Purgatory and Paradise, and not merely the concept of final judgment about eternal life or eternal death and the hint at possible punishment after death.1 The purely political implications of Plato’s myth in the last book of the Republic, as well as the concluding parts of Phaidon and Gorgias, are indisputable. In the Republic, it4 corresponds to the story of the cave, which is the center of the whole work and which is not a myth but an allegory, destined5 for the few who are able,6 without hope7 or fear to perform8 the Platonic periagôgé9, the turning around from the shadowy life of seeming reality to the clear sky of ideas. Life with the11 ideas, while it clearly alienated them from12 the life of the polis, taught the few13 true standards of all life, including political affairs, in which, however, they were15 no longer to16 be |24 interested for their own sake17. Only the fear of being ruled by the multitude could arouse the few to fulfill their political duties. These18 who could understand the story of the cave were not supposed to believe the concluding myth about final reward and punishment. Not only did those who had19 grasped the truth of the ideas as transcendent standards need no more20 tangible transcendence like an explicit21 life after death; it would not even have made22 much sense insofar as23 the story of the cave already describes life on earth as a kind of Underworld, and this sense is reinforced by24 Plato’s use of the words eid ^ olon and25 skia which were the key words of Homer’s description of Hades in the Odyssey, so that26 the whole story reads27 like an exact28 reply to Homer:30 not the soul is the shadow and not32 its life after death the purposeless insubstantial motion33 in the Underworld34, but the bodily life of ordinary mortals who do not succeed35 in turning away from the cave of earthly life; our life on earth is life in an Underworld36, our body is the shadow and our only reality is the soul. Since the truth of the ideas is self-revealing and therefore37 self-evident, the true standards for earthly life can never be satisfactorily argued out and demonstrated. The multitude which lacks the eye for the invisible measurement of all visible things, needs belief in a stark bodily transcendence in which it does not hold truth itself but only its “myth.”38 | [keine Entsprechung vorhanden] | [metamark (unknown)]The purely political implications of Plato’s myth in the last book of the Republic, as well as the concluding parts of Phaidon and Gorgias, are indisputable. In the Republic, it4 corresponds to the story of the cave, which is the center of the whole work and which is not a myth but an allegory, destined5 for the few who are able,6 without hope7 or fear to perform8 the Platonic περιαγωγή periagôgé9 [gap], the turning around from the shadowy life of seeming reality to the clear sky of ideas. Life with the11 ideas, while it clearly alienated them from12 the life of the polis, taught the few13 true standards of all life, including political affairs, in which, however, they were15 no longer to16 be interested for their own sake17. Only the fear of being ruled by the multitude could arouse the few to fulfill their political duties. Those18 who could understand the story of the cave were not supposed to believe the concluding myth about final reward and punishment. Not only did who had19 grasped the truth of the ideas as transcendent standards need no more20 tangible like an explicit21 life after death; it would not even have made22 much sense insofar as23 the story of the cave already describes life on earth as a kind of Underworld, and this |20 sense is reinforced by24 Plato’s use of the words εἴδωλον eidôlon and σκιά25 skia which were the key words of Homer’s description of Hades in the Odyssey, so that26 the whole story reads27 like a reversal of, and probably was meant as a28 reply to,29 Homer:30 not the soul is the shadow and not32 its life after death the purposeless insubstantial motion33 in the Underworld34, but the bodily life of ordinary mortals who do not succeed35 in turning away from the cave of earthly life; our life on earth is life in an Underworld36, our body is the shadow and our only reality is the soul. Since the truth of the ideas is self-revealing and therefore37 self-evident, the true standards for earthly life can never be satisfactorily argued [metamark ]out and demonstrated. The multitude which lacks the eye for the invisible measurement of all visible things, needs belief in a stark bodily transcendence in which it does not perceive truth itself but only its “myth”.38 | The purely political implications of Plato’s myth in the last book of the Republic, as well as the concluding parts of Phaidon and Gorgias, are indisputable. In the Republic this myth4 corresponds to the story of the cave, which is the center of the whole work. An allegory, the cave story is intended5 for the few who are able to perform6 without fear7 or hope of an Hereafter8 the Platonic periagogé9, the turning around from the shadowy life of seeming reality to confront10 the clear sky of “11ideas.” Only those few will understand12 the true standards of all life, including political affairs, in which last14, however, they will15 no longer be interested per se17. To be sure, those18 who could understand the story of the cave were not supposed to believe the concluding myth about final reward and punishment, because whoever19 grasped the truth of the ideas as transcendent standards no longer required any20 tangible standards such as21 life after death. The concept of life after death does not make22 much sense in their case since23 the story of the cave already describes life on earth as a kind of underworld. In fact,24 Plato’s use of the words eidōlon and25 skia which were the key words of Homer’s description of Hades in the Odyssey makes26 the whole story read27 like a reversal of, and a28 reply to,29 Homer; it is30 not the soul which31 is the shadow, nor is it32 its life after death in substantial motion34, but the bodily life of ordinary mortals who do not succeed35 in turning away from the cave of earthly life; our life on earth is life in an underworld36, our body is the shadow and our only reality is the soul. Since the truth of the ideas is self-evident, the true standards for earthly life can never be satisfactorily argued out and demonstrated. |